Image: Bernard Picart, The Muses warming themselves by the fire of bad books
Rumours have it that there is a crisis in the Humanities. That news is not new. According to one tract, there are four reasons for it:
- The classics are edited badly.
- Scholars promise too much, and then cannot live up to the expectations.
- Scholars quarrel too much, and thereby give the Humanities a bad name.
- There is no money in it.
That is
what theologist and journalist Jean le Clerc, one of the most prominent voices
in the Republic of Letters of his day, wrote in 1699 in the first volume of his
Parrhesiana. Especially point 4 still
rings familiar.
The most
recent episode in that crisis seems to have taken place last year, as a wave of
student protests washed over Canada, the Netherlands and the UK opposing budget
cuts, college fee rises and staff and student disempowerment especially in the
non-STEM disciplines. No one complained about bad editions of the classics, but
everyone involved seemed to agree that the university was not living up to its
promises and instead leaving staff and students in the cold. One widely shared
article compared academia to a Ponzi scheme, since it asks students to bury
themselves in debt with the promise of jobs that they will rarely get, and if
so only after years in graduate and post-doc limbo. If devoting your life to
learning becomes like borrowing money from the mob, then something has gone
gravely wrong indeed.
But in
between 1699 and 2015, there have been some other crises in the Humanities as
well. The Jesuits were expulsed and their colleges closed. The National
Convention effectively rendered all French universities obsolete in 1791. The
Republic of Letters disappeared, or diluted, or imploded, or at any rate ceased
to be the vibrant network of exchange that it was in the Early Modern age. Half
the German universities perished between 1795 and 1818. The 1930s and 40s were
not a particularly good time for the peaceful study of arts and letters either.
And yet, we still exist. Somehow,
amidst eternally recurrent crisis, the Humanities continue to expand and multiply.
When Jean le Clerc wrote, there were approx. 1,200 active scholars around
Europe; in 2015, that was less than the number of people defending a PhD in the
Humanities in France, Germany, or the UK in one year. Maybe our troubles would
be worse if the Humanities were not in
crisis.
The
exponential expansion is not all that surprising really, since the Humanities
deal with things that bear meaning. Books, texts, images, languages, political
events, more of that ilk. And those things just keep on growing. You don’t
really need to do anything to watch new history, new texts, new images appear.
And to preserve some of that, you need people to interpret, describe, and
classify it. So there will always be a task for humanities scholars as
store-keepers of things that bear meaning. That store-keeping role, for that
matter, was described 250 years ago already in Diderot and d’Alembert’s Encyclopédie,
article Érudition.
The problem with that role is, much as we’d like to, you can’t store everything. The complaint that has been issued against the Humanities at least since 1637 is that the critical study of old texts and artifacts is a dusty affair and always lags behind events. Most often, this is true. Stores gather dust; descriptions always lag behind events. All that accumulation of texts, artifacts and descriptions of texts and artifacts makes little sense if it doesn’t lead to new ideas, or doesn’t come with a good case for why this is relevant. There is a kind of cycle of diminishing returns to the store-keeper conception of the Humanities: new insights lead to new accumulations, but as the new material heaps up it also adds less and less relevance, and dissatisfaction with that situation leads to new critical insight which also sends some of the old data to the dustbin. Undsoweiter.
Against
complaints of dustiness, it helps to emphasize that sometimes those critical
insights from the Humanities have had impact in the real world. The Reformation
was the direct offspring of humanism and text criticism. Modern bureaucracy was
invented by 15th-century humanists. So was secondary education.
Almost all great Enlightenment thinkers were at least part-time historians and
articulated their ideas through historical works, if they did not draw them
from historical studies. The great political ideologies that emerged in the
wake of the French Revolution – liberalism, conservatism, nationalism,
radicalism, and after that, socialism – are at least linked to historical and
philological studies. This is not necessarily the nicest argument for the
Humanities imaginable, because anyone who has opinions hates at least one or
two of the above, but you can hardly dismiss them as irrelevant.
Another
complaint against the Humanities is that they are not proper sciences. As
statisticians tend to say: “anecdote is not the singular of data”. Defenders of
the Humanities, faced with this complaint, sometimes feel the need to appeal to
some ‘hermeneutic method’ purportedly invented around 1800. There are two
reasons why this is a bad strategy. The first is that the ‘hermeneutic
tradition’ was not a tradition before Hanns-Georg Gadamer’s Wahrheit und Methode of 1960, and in
spite of its claim to open-mindedness, Gadamer’s notion of hermeneutics is
inextricably linked up with an ink-black Heideggerian conservatism. The second
is that reading a few old books from the period around 1800 teaches you
differently, because those books are filled with terms like hypothesis,
anomaly, conjecture, inference, raissonnement.
Edward Gibbon even formulated something dangerously close to Popper’s
falsification criterion in an essay he wrote at age 21, when he described the
task of the ‘true critic’ as ‘daring to sacrifice your most audacious
hypothesis’.
According
to a somewhat narrow-minded definition of ‘science’ the Humanities indeed can’t
be proper sciences, since we’re dealing with things that bear meaning. And you
can’t measure meaning. So you have to work with functionally vague concepts
rather than with decontextualized units and measures, just as you do in
everyday language. This doesn’t mean that we stop formulating hypotheses or
drawing conclusions. Rather, it means that what we do in the Humanities is
essentially argumentative, more so
than in the exact sciences, since an argument is something that you can disagree
with. The problem with functionally vague concepts is that you constantly need
to disambiguate them, and that you can’t build long chains of inference with
them, because the vagueness increases at every step. The product of vagueness
and vagueness is more vagueness.
For the
same reason, there is no point in a self-conception of the Humanities that
makes a virtue out of finding ever new interpretations. The more
interpretations you give, the harder they can be distinguished from one
another. If you have a dozen interpretations, that is half a dozen too many.
The question not: how could you also look
at it, but: why is that insight relevant?
Thus, there
is no way of creating meaning, in the semantic sense, without making things
matter. Meaning requires argumentation in order to make it explicit, and
argumentation requires motivation. That motivation, ultimately, cannot rely on
some notion of self-formation, edification, or Bildung. Not because becoming a fuller, better informed person is
not a legitimate ideal – it is – but because there is no way of getting rid of
the better-than-thou once you
instrumentalize it in this way. You can only make things matter if you come up
with something significantly new, instead of congratulating yourself on your
critical spirit and your deep hermeneutic understanding. All the same, the
motivation of what we say also demands that we do not remain silent about our
ideals. It’s just that those ideals are not rock bottom; nobody cares how gebildet, or critical, or engagé you are. What is needed is something of ‘the old made new’:
new old facts mixed with interesting new ideas.
There is
another important task for the Humanities there, next to describing and
conserving. It’s not about interpretation but about argumentation. Once you’ve
stopped being interesting you’ve basically stopped reasoning. So the real game
is about clarifying concepts and introducing new ideas. About explaining why
something matters without chewing out second-hand chewing gum. And that will
always be a problematic affair. In that regard, ‘crisis’ is the normal
condition in the Humanities, and it will not go away. So maybe we should learn
to love the monster and embrace that condition. Which is not to say that we
should cheerfully embark on an academic Ponzi scheme.
Geen opmerkingen:
Een reactie posten